Intelligence and Emergence
- Intelligence is deeply ingrained in the multi-scale architecture of living organisms. It exists from molecular networks up. AI can help understand biology, and biology can inspire new AI.
- Emergence is important, but biology’s key is closed-loop, goal-directed (cybernetic) agents at *all* scales, not just emergent outcomes. These agents actively reduce errors from set points, using energy to achieve goals.
- Higher levels of organization can do causal work that’s not reducible to lower levels (referencing Julio Tononi and Eric Hoel’s work on Information Theory). This can be mathematically determined, not just philosophically debated.
- Membrane voltage, a high-level aggregate, is more useful for regenerative medicine and other interventions than tracking individual ion positions. This highlights higher-level causal power.
Agency and Observer Relativity
- Agency is best described along a continuum (a “persuadability continuum”), not as a binary property. Sharp categories are imposed by observers on continuous phenomena.
- Levels of system, is based of what is being observed. It can shift with what the observer.
- The claim that a system occupies a particular place on this agency continuum is observer-relative. It’s not an objective fact, but depends on the observer’s model and how well that model lets them interact with the system.
- A crucial point is that the system *itself* can be a valid observer, creating internal models and controlling itself. This “self-observation” is a key aspect of agency.
- Making the claims about systems are done so in respect of a hypothesis on an individual system by a researcher/obvserver.
Physicalism, Reductionism, and Matter
- Challenging reductionist physicalism doesn’t negate physicalism itself. It argues that matter is capable of far more than often assumed, including higher-level organization with non-reducible causal power.
- Saying an entity isn’t made of a kind of matter isn’t helpful in describing intelligence, given that all things have the same underlying “stuff”.
- “Pseudo-problems” arise from making objective claims in this area. Specifying the vantage point (observer) clarifies many issues.
- Any computation or intelligence isn’t necessarily reliant upon some sort of external observers but instead it itself can observe, as this defines this form of being (a legitimate entity in-and-of-itself).
Phase Transitions and Continuity
- While sharp, non-linear changes in behavior (akin to phase transitions) exist in AI and other fields, biological cognition appears more continuous. Sharpness in phase transitions often increases with system size.
- It’s difficult to pinpoint a specific “phase transition” where cognition *suddenly* emerges in development or evolution. The substrate is continuous; it’s a transformation of the *same* material.
- Attributing cognitive capabilities to single cells is controversial, but critics need to provide a concrete explanation of *how* and *when* full cognition emerges during development or evolution. Simply stating this point in time isn’t concrete.
- This doesn’t equate the lack of understanding transitions in understanding and quantifying them for future predictions (on future research, technologies, etc etc).
Defining and Measuring Intelligence
- Even gene regulatory networks (seemingly mechanical) exhibit various forms of learning (e.g., associative conditioning), showcasing non-zero intelligence at very low levels.
- The absolute minimum of intelligence likely involves: (1) some level of goal-directedness (least action principles, even in particles) and (2) some indeterminacy (local conditions not fully determining behavior).
- This doesn’t need to equate to 0 levels. Even at atomic scales and even in a “cognitive vacuum” these principles can exist as its “basement”, so long there are actions, reactions and movements of its components.
- Measuring intelligence is taking an IQ test ourselves. We must define a problem space, identify the system’s policy, and test the policy’s “cleverness.” We might not always recognize intelligence, especially outside familiar domains.
- Intelligence doesn’t rely on conventional intelligence such as with brains.
- Researchers must actively observe, analyze and quantify intelligence in non-human systems by defining their: behavior and environmental space (that it is doing it’s intelligent “stuff”).
- Intelligence is related to its capabilities in such a “problem space” and may depend, for example, on navigating this space and/or physiology.
- A continuum of competencies exists, from simple systems following energy gradients (like magnets) to complex systems overcoming obstacles to reach goals (like Romeo and Juliet). The is quantifiable in this way.
- Research shows that there is intelligence in simpler systems.
- The challenge is perturbation. It changes goals of individual parts that normally seem fixed on fixed behaviours.
- A system’s intelligence is revealed by challenging its “normal” behavior with perturbations. Often, systems are more capable than initially assumed. This makes assumptions hardwired (fixed on set behaviours, that would have difficulty adjusting/doing so within the limits/timescale for measuring and/or perturbation.
Goal-Directedness, Anthropomorphism, and Interaction
- A system’s “goal” is a useful lens or perspective for prediction and control, not necessarily an objective, discoverable fact. Positing a goal and competencies helps us interact effectively.
- Such can also involve more complicated relationships than what would be considered standard such as “friendships” if they allow for an optimized control and behaviour, for both sides involved in a system.
- “Anthropomorphism” isn’t a useful concept. We should make *specific*, testable claims about a system’s capabilities (human, robot, cell, etc.) and empirically determine their validity. We often *underestimate* intelligence, especially in biology.
- The assumption on an entities “naturality” also influences people on intelligence due to biases in a pre-garden assumption that doesn’t account that nature (life) doesn’t set you up, as Evolution simply aims for replicating with variations.
On Natural, Biomass and Goals
- Nature’s is set to survival by the “means of replication”, which is done from stochastic-gradient descent.
- Different solutions can apply/be found on how goals and intelligences can manifest that differs from humans.
- Humans desire/instinctually don’t enjoy nature because their current goals, even before major technological advances, often had goals (in many examples given, even primitive ones such as an umbrella, showed examples and reasoning on why and how to differ goals).
- Humans don’t have innate, fixed and/or objective/optimal goals (even pre-Garden as there isn’t necessarily something objective to begin with (on what would constitute these parameters).
- Humans also can influence these biases as with tools or modifications of any level.
Transhumanism and Categories
- Biology is highly interoperable. We can create chimeras/hybrids between biological tissues and machines, blurring boundaries between “human” and “machine.” There is it continuous with many variances in percentage. This challenges binary categories.
- A goal of intelligence research can mean to “better what is defined as a natural body” (of people for example).
- There exist human, biological extensions to even radical extremes that makes distinctions for transhumanism that blurs these parameters of distinction.
- Categorizing organisms/systems as natural kinds (with sharp, inherent boundaries) is limiting. Biology and technology push these boundaries, demanding a more nuanced perspective.
- “Natural” is often undesirable. Evolution optimizes for biomass, not human happiness or fulfillment. We can (and should) strive to do better than “natural” through science and technology.
- What is viewed as unnatural could well be natural too due to emergent, external factors that affect changes in human’s systems in question and the research or development being studied or discussed.